The discourse of multiculturalism, often regarded as
characteristically American, has in recent years steadily gained ground in
Europe. This can be seen as a belated response to the often striking
transformation of the metropolitan Lebenswelt by the inflow of
millions from Asia, Africa, the Antilles and the Middle East. Decades of
friction between majorities and minorities in the streets, on
the labour market, in public housing, over access to welfare and in schools
have thrown up fractured ethno-landscapes all across the continent. At a time
when the orthodoxies of the market have all but eliminated any alternatives
from the political field, both admirers and detractors of multiculturalism
insist on the increasing centrality of a new axis of group
differentiation and the problems that it poses to inherited
conceptions of national
identity. The presence of large
immigrant
communities in the EU, often dating from the
twilight era of colonialism, acquires a more pregnant significance—it is
often felt—in an era of globalization, as the main vectors of economic
development, geopolitics and mass culture all seem to point to a featureless
horizon beyond the nation-state. Immigrants from the non-European
world appear to introduce an extra element of uncertainty into this transition,
perhaps threatening to derail the train to Euroland altogether.
In Rethinking Multiculturalism the eminently
establishment figure of Bhikhu Parekh—Vice-Chancellor of Baroda University,
Deputy Chair of the Commission for Racial Equality in the UK, and peer in the
British House of Lords—attempts to relate such European issues to North
American and Indian experiences. His aim is to propose a comprehensive
normative framework for addressing ethno-religious and racial conflicts in
liberal democracies. The practical objective of securing a peaceful
and inclusive civic life overrides any temptation on Parekh’s part to dwell
at length on incommensurable values. His construction of
multiculturalism eschews any deep theory of culture, using the term to refer
simply to communal modes of being in the world that generate complex but
manageable problems of inter-group communication and cohabitation. The communal
cultures he discusses usually emerge out of a fusion of ethnicity and
religion. Loyalty to the way of life they prescribe is represented not
as an adhesion to transcendental imperatives, but rather as the expression of
an irreplaceable quotidian experience.
But if such cultures are rich in themselves, they are
also multistranded, like pieces of rope, and by weaving together certain
strands from each, a durable and colourful fabric of society can be made. Since
cultures of this sort tend to be most palpable when they exclude outsiders, it
might be objected that multiculturalism—however good for keeping the
peace—is unlikely to be quite so good for the integrity of the cultures
themselves. But Parekh is confident that an open-minded dialogue between
majorities and minorities will not only preserve, but refine the
ethno-religious traditions of each. Conceding that too much mixing might dilute
what is valuable in any particular culture, he insists that doctrinaire
universalism and its opposite, chauvinistic culturalism are
worse. By way of demonstration, he takes the reader on a flat-footed tour
through the gallery of Great Philosophers—from Plato to
Rawls—stopping here and there to explain to what degree a given
thinker failed to grasp the mellow verities of the middle ground, either
because he leaned too far in the direction of universalistic monism,
or alternately too far in the direction of relativism.
Ostensibly, Parekh’s book sets out to offer a critique of
contemporary liberals who fail to recognize the impossibility of public
neutrality between different conceptions of the good life, according
surreptitious priority to their own values of autonomy, human rights
and distributive justice. Granting without difficulty a minimum of
universal prohibitions—against slavery, torture, and the like—he contends
that liberals illegitimately expand the empire of rights in ways that often
violate the customary norms of traditional communities. This looks like the
stuff of a sharp philosophical conflict, but when Parekh elaborates on it, the
upshot is little that really departs from actually existing Anglo-American
liberalism. Indeed he maintains that, at least in Western countries, a public
commitment to liberal values must be accepted since a thorough-going neutrality
between liberal and non-liberal conceptions of legitimacy is impossible. This
turns out to be more than just a matter of expediency: for all practical
purposes Parekh appears to believe—though he does not say so—that liberal
values are closest to what we all know to be universally valid.
His principal objection to mainstream liberalism is simply that
it does not have a theory of cultural groups and the rights that they can
legitimately claim. But the criteria he suggests for recognition of such groups
prove to be a confused medley of the conservative, the sentimental and the
completely evasive, embracing traditional communities, social pariahs, or just
those who contribute something valuable to society: Orthodox Jews,
Untouchables, African Americans, and any legitimate claimant to special status.
Unwilling to yield to ‘postmodern’ conceptions of fluid and hybridized
identities, Parekh seeks to be both firm and flexible here, distinguishing
between multiculturalism proper—that is, relations between ‘communal’
cultures—and mere subcultural diversity. Although he introduces other
criteria to allow for affirmative action, his theory of group entitlements is
heavily biased towards more traditional cultures. The same list is visible in
his treatment of current inter-cultural controversies. Most of the cases he
discusses involve divisions between European national majorities and Muslim,
Hindu or Sikh minorities over public symbolism and the allocation of public
resources. The issues on which he focuses are scarves, turbans, funerals and
funding of religious schools. On these he sides with immigrant communities,
while at the same time explaining that Western societies can legitimately
accord priority to their own traditional institutions, creeds and symbols. By
extension, Parekh expresses muted approval for the Israeli Law of Return as a
culture-preserving measure.
When it comes to ethno-religious practices or rules governing
the position of women, Parekh has little hesitation in appealing to
universal moral norms; and though he rhetorically sides with
protesters against Rushdie’s Satanic Verses, maintaining that the
Indian government was right to ban the novel, he ends by concluding that it
would probably be sensible to abolish blasphemy laws altogether. The sum of his
recommendations could, in effect, be accepted by virtually any right-thinking
upholder of Westminster values. Billed as a critical reconsideration of liberal
premisses, the objective of Rethinking Multiculturalism could be more
accurately described as the de-Westernization of liberalism—a stealth
liberalism capable of integrating variously devout immigrants into unevenly
secular European societies. Reform of too-extreme dogmas or customs, of course,
he believes essential, to bring the culture of traditional religious
communities into line with the requirements of the modern world. The end result
would, in a best-case scenario, be a continent in which all could take a modest
pride in their ethnic or religious patrimonies, untainted by aggressive
fanaticism or corrosive cynicism.
Multiculturalism, so understood, is an unobjectionable
extension of contemporary liberalism, for which Parekh—who makes no claims as
a radical—cannot be faulted. It is quite another matter for the Left to make
this outlook its own. A glance at the differing situations in Europe and
America is enough to make this plain. In both, the idea of multiculturalism
appeals to a certain sensibility on the Left, as a higher form of anti-racism
that meshes with the culturalist common sense of the time: that the order of
human things is a cultural artefact and therefore that the fundamental
conflicts within it are fought over representation, identity and
lifestyle. One corollary is that a good society can be established without any
coercive redistribution of property. Another is that religion is neither
obscurantist nor an opiate, but rather a form of identity and a way of
life—just like class, nation or sexual preference. In Europe, it is the
latter deduction that is politically most salient, as the critical stance of
the Enlightenment towards religion has been widely jettisoned. It is now
standard for religious protectionism of one kind or another to be dressed up as
anti-racism. A paradigm case is the denunciation of any criticism of Judaism or
Zionism as anti-Semitic, or of Islam as arabophobic. Religious faiths may, in
fact, offer defensive identities for vulnerable immigrant communities. But the
same creeds can be weapons of vicious repression in their homelands—and that
there can be links between the two the followers of Khomeini or Kahane amply
demonstrate.