Both the strengths of the New Left’s critique of domination and its underlying weaknesses reveal themselves, with particular sharpness and clarity, in the attraction of the New Left to an intellectual tradition seemingly resistant to radical reinterpretation yet essential, it turned out, to the new theory of revolution—the theory of cultural revolution—that haunted the imagination of the sixties. What brought about this improbable alliance of psychoanalysis and cultural radicalism, of Freud and Marx? We seem to have here a remarkable instance of the attraction of opposites. Freud puts more stress on human limitations than on human potential, he has no faith in social progress, and he insists that civilization is founded on repression. There isn’t much here, at first glance, that would commend itself to reformers or revolutionaries—and in the last analysis, the theorists of the Freudian left in one way or another have had to get around or explain away the deterministic, tragic side of Freud’s thought, which has more in common with St. Augustine and Calvin than with Marx. Why then did the left bother with psychoanalysis in the first place?
The reasons lie in the political events of the twenties and early thirties. The failure of a socialist revolution to materialize out of the chaos of World War I, when all the objective conditions in Central and Western Europe seemed conducive to a turn to the left, prompted investigations into the subjective conditions impeding social and political progress. The rise of fascism seemed to provide additional evidence of deep-seated psychological resistance to liberating change. It raised doubts about the inevitability of historical progress and about the adequacy of Marxist orthodoxy, which could find nothing more illuminating to say about fascism than that it represented the last phase of a decadent capitalism. The solidification of the Stalinist regime in the Soviet Union provided a further challenge to the myth of progress. Opponents of Stalinism had to ask themselves why the Russian Revolution, like so many revolutions in the past, had appeared to end in a regression to authoritarian rule. A kind of repetition-compulsion seemed to be at work in history: each attempt to get rid of authoritarianism succeeded only in reconstituting it on a new basis. Revolutions had evidently failed to attack authoritarianism at its psychological source. They had brought new classes to power without changing the underlying structure of power itself. They had modified institutions without breaking the pattern of domination and submission that underlay those institutions. In order to understand the self-defeating quality of past revolutions and to lay the psychological groundwork for a new kind of revolution that would put an end to domination once and for all, it was evidently imperative to understand the psychology of power; and psychoanalysis, it seemed, had more to say on this subject than any other theory of the mind.
For those who sought to grasp the underlying resistance to change that revealed itself even in movements ostensibly devoted to change, the attraction of Freud’s work lay in its attack on the illusion of psychic autonomy. Men need masters because they are not masters of themselves: this became the central contention of the Freudian left. Freud’s theory, in this view, provides the deepest glimpses into the divided self. It shows how society enters and deforms the individual psyche: not through indoctrination or cultural ‘conditioning’, but through the deeper mechanisms of repression and sublimation. The conviction that unites thinkers as diverse as Herbert Marcuse, R. D. Laing and Jacques Lacan is that psychoanalysis traces the origin of intrapsychic conflict to the conditions under which social authority recreates itself in the unconscious mind, and specifically to the institution of the patriarchal family, which crushes the revolt of the son against the father, saddles the son with a guilty conscience, and makes him grow up to become a tyrant in his own right.
Much of this ground had been covered already in the thirties and forties by Wilhelm Reich, who might be called—except for the inappropriateness of patriarchal imagery in this context—the founding father of the Freudian left. At times the work of radical Freudians in our own time looks like a rehash of Reich. But even Reich had not gone far enough to suit his followers. According to Norman O. Brown, ‘Reich was right in arguing that to fulfill its own therapeutic promise, psychoanalysis has to
The cultural revolution, then—the program of deep structural change envisioned by the radical Freudian left—went far beyond a mere ‘sexual revolution.’ Its task, as these theorists saw it, was not to set aside more opportunities for erotic indulgence, as a momentary release from the demands of alienated labor, but to eroticize work itself. The point was not to enlarge the domain of leisure but to abolish the very distinction between work and leisure, to make work into play, and to get rid of the aggressive, domineering attitude toward nature that informs the present organization of work. It was partly in order to explain the origins of that attitude that theorists of the New Left turned to Freud. In other words, they turned to Freud for very good reasons. Unfortunately they brought with them a set of assumptions that owed more to the socialistic theory of the family (as Max Weber once called it) than to the founder of psychoanalysis.footnote4 Their attempt to base a general theory of culture on psychoanalysis, or to read psychoanalysis itself as a general theory of culture, led them further and further away from the critical core of psychoanalysis: its interpretation of clinical data. What began as a fruitful confrontation between psychoanalysis and Marxism ended in a reassimilation of psychoanalytic ideas to an older socialist critique of the patriarchal family—a critique that is becoming increasingly irrelevant to
Although it is difficult to generalize about the various schools of thought on the Freudian left—followers of Marcuse, followers of Brown, Laingians, Lacanians, radical feminists, socialist feminists—they all share the central premise that the patriarchal family is the root of organized oppression. It is important to remember that this idea has a long history that antedates Freud and has continued to develop independently of Freud. From the beginning, it had pronounced feminist and socialist overtones. Bachofen’s study of mother-right, Lewis Henry Morgan’s study of archaic kinship terminology, Engels’s analysis of the connections between the family, private property and the state all appeared to call into question the universality of monogamy and to trace its rise to the subjugation of women. The myth of matriarchal origins has remained attractive to feminists ever since, long after its abandonment by anthropologists. But even without the corollary of a matriarchal stage of social development allegedly antedating the patriarchal stage, the idea that oppression originates in the family continues to find widespread acceptance on the left, in large part because it seems to explain the rise and persistence of Faustian, acquisitive, aggressive, domineering character traits. Not just the radical left but the political culture of liberalism has been deeply coloured by a revolt against the discredited patriarchal authority of priests and poets and divinely anointed kings, and the critique of the family represents one of the most enduring ideological expressions of this revolt. Indeed the imagery of revolutionary brotherhood, which has been bound up with modern state-building since the time of the French revolution, derives its emotional energy from the tension between the overthrow and reconstitution of patriarchal authority. Given the number of modern states that have originated in revolutions, it is not surprising that so many modern thinkers have associated the origin of civilization itself with an act of rebellion against the father, followed by the reimposition of his authority in new forms.
Freud’s own theory of the primal horde incorporates much of this revolutionary imagery as well as the formal theories of nineteenth-century anthropologists. It is easy to see attraction of this Freudian creation myth for the New Left. It not only implicates the family in the origins of a repressive civilization, but for the first time it spells out the psychological linkages between them: linkages between political history and the family. The sons overthrow the father but internalize his authority and reimpose it on women and children. The original revolution thus becomes the prototype of failed revolutions ever since. The uprising of the rebellious sons momentarily breaks ‘the chain of domination,’ according to Marcuse; ‘then the new freedom is again suppressed—this time by their own authority and action.’ Once established, the ‘rhythm of liberation and domination’ repeats itself throughout history—as in the life and death of Jesus, which Marcuse interprets as a struggle against the patriarchal laws in the name of love, a struggle betrayed by Christ’s