What has come to be known over the last ten years or so as ‘the labour process debate’ has been, literally, very much an academic exercise. And now its academic participants are pronouncing its end: ‘It is not perhaps an exaggeration to claim that the labour process bandwagon has run into the sand. Indeed, the catalogue of amendments and criticisms attaching to labour process theory has led a number of critics to call for little less than the abandonment of “labour process theory”footnote1.’ Should the Left care? Many of the arguments put forward in the post-Braverman labour process debate have had the effect of displacing the production process from the centre of Marxist analysis. In that sense, they carry political implications which dovetail only too neatly into some major diversionary strategies prevalent on the left today. Such strategies, which appear to provide a left-wing parallel to the political and industrial processes of deconstruction under Thatcherism, reflect an increasingly market-oriented approach to the issues of capitalist accumulation and crisis. These approaches are both pessimistic and optimistic in their conclusions. Their pessimism lies in the argument that there is no conceivable political future in the traditional organizations of the working class;footnote2 their optimism in ‘small is beautiful’ marketing and production strategies such as the ‘flexible specialization’ of gleb’s London Industrial Strategy, which when examined closely bear a remarkable resemblance to the Thatcherite project of deconstructing the economy.

It will be argued here that the issue of the labour process has not become irrelevant to modern-day capitalism, but that post-Braverman conceptualizations of the labour process have consistently misunderstood, ignored, or misrepresented its true relevance. In place of the prevailing view, with its vaguely ‘radical’ overtones, which situates something called ‘control’ at the centre of the labour process, there will be an attempt to restore a Marxist understanding of valorization and exploitation as central to the operation of the capitalist labour process and to the politics of workers’ resistance.

Paul Thompson, in a recent paper which attempts to counter current prognostications of ‘crisis’ within the labour process debate, defines the ‘core theory’ within that debate as having ‘always been associated with the issues of deskilling and managerial control’.footnote3 Certainly, in the voluminous body of work produced since 1974 in response to Harry Braverman’s Labor and Monopoly Capital, one major theme has emerged and remained supreme, the issue of ‘control’, from the perspective of both management and workers. It has by no means been clear exactly what, either theoretically or empirically, ‘control’ is actually about. Nevertheless it has remained the pivot around which both criticism of Braverman—for after initial enthusiasm the commentary on Braverman has been almost universally hostile—and response to these criticisms have revolved.

Put simply, the central criticism of Braverman’s analysis has been that his (alleged) portrayal of ‘a single, overall trend—an imperative of control of the labour process’ ignores the reality and complexity of worker resistance.footnote4 Classical theorists of the labour process, such as Braverman and by implication Marx, are criticized for a representation of capitalist ‘control’ as one-dimensional and overwhelming, untrammelled by worker resistance. Early proponents of this view, such as Andrew Friedman and Richard Edwards,footnote5 have in their turn been criticized for depicting ‘control’ too simplistically. All these arguments have in common the assumption that ‘control’ constitutes the principal dynamic at work in the capitalist labour process.

The preoccupation with ‘control’ has been so tenacious that even when, as in the work of John Roemer, the object is specifically to understand exploitation, the labour process makes a (tangential) appearance in the form—and only in the form—of a coercive power struggle: ‘Although coercion in the workplace exists also in capitalism, such coercion is of secondary importance in understanding exploitation and class. It is a mistake to elevate the struggle between worker and capitalist in the process of production to a more privileged position in the theory than the differential ownership of productive assets. These results thus force a re-evaluation of the classical belief that the labour process is at the centre of the Marxian analysis of exploitation and class, a belief that has become even more prominent since the pioneering work of Braverman.’footnote6 Roemer, having (correctly) observed that ‘extra-economic’ coercion is not essential to capitalist exploitation in the sense that it is to, say, feudalism, evidently sees nothing of importance in the labour process apart from this (inessential) coercive ‘struggle between worker and capitalist’.